What is Russell's Paradox?

Declan Davies
Declan Davies
Experienced quantitative analyst, former math Olympiad.

Alright, let's talk about the fascinating "Russell's Paradox."

What is Russell's Paradox?

Hey, this question might sound profound, but its core idea can actually be understood through a very classic story, known as the "Barber Paradox."

The Barber's Story

Imagine a small village with only one barber. He was very proud and established a rule for himself:

I only shave men in this village who do not shave themselves.

Sounds reasonable, right? He caters to those who don't do it themselves.

Okay, so here's the problem:

Should the barber shave himself?

Let's analyze this:

  1. If he shaves himself:

    • According to his rule, he only shaves "those who do not shave themselves."
    • Now that he has shaved himself, he is "a person who shaves himself."
    • This violates his own rule! Therefore, he cannot shave himself.
  2. If he does not shave himself:

    • Then, he belongs to the category of "people who do not shave themselves."
    • And his rule is to shave all such people.
    • Therefore, he must shave himself.

You see, this leads to a vicious cycle:

  • If he shaves, he must not shave.
  • If he does not shave, he must shave.

No matter which choice is made, it leads to a contradiction. This is a paradox. The barber's rule is logically impossible.


From the Barber to Mathematics

Alright, the barber's story is done. Now let's translate this story into mathematical language, which is the true form of Russell's Paradox.

Before Russell proposed this paradox, mathematicians (especially Cantor, the founder of set theory) believed that anything we could think of or describe could be grouped into a "set." For example, "the set of all integers" or "the set of all red things" – these were considered perfectly normal.

Then, Russell divided sets into two categories:

  1. Category 1: "Normal sets," which are sets that do not contain themselves.

    • Most sets are like this. For instance, "the set of all apples" – the set itself is not an apple, so it does not contain itself. Similarly, "the set of all humans" – the set itself is not a human, so it does not contain itself.
  2. Category 2: "Abnormal sets," which are sets that do contain themselves.

    • These sets are more abstract but can be constructed. For example, "the set of all non-apples." This set itself "is not an apple," so it meets the condition to be included within itself; thus, it contains itself.

After classifying them, Russell posed a question identical to the barber's paradox. He defined a special set, which we'll call set R:

Set R = The set of all "normal sets."

In other words: R contains all sets that do not contain themselves.

Now, the crucial question arises again:

Does set R contain itself?

Let's analyze this again:

  1. If R contains itself:

    • According to the definition of R, it only contains "sets that do not contain themselves."
    • Since R now contains itself, it no longer meets the condition for inclusion in R.
    • Therefore, it cannot contain itself. A contradiction!
  2. If R does not contain itself:

    • Then R is a "set that does not contain itself."
    • According to the definition of R, it is supposed to contain all such sets.
    • Therefore, it must contain itself. Another contradiction!

You see, it's identical to the Barber Paradox. This set R is like that unfortunate barber; its very existence leads to a logical breakdown.

What are the implications of this paradox?

You might say, "Isn't this just a word game?"

At the time, the introduction of this paradox was nothing short of a bombshell, directly shaking the foundations of modern mathematics – set theory. It demonstrated that the prevailing belief among mathematicians that "any property can define a set" was fundamentally flawed, containing a fatal "bug."

To fix this bug, mathematicians later "patched" set theory, developing more rigorous axiomatic set theory (such as the ZFC axiom system widely used today). Simply put, sets could no longer be defined arbitrarily; instead, they had to adhere to stricter rules, thereby preventing the emergence of "monsters" like set R that could trigger paradoxes.


One-sentence summary

Russell's Paradox, by constructing a "set of all sets that do not contain themselves," revealed that in naive set theory, a seemingly reasonable definition could lead to an unsolvable logical contradiction, thereby prompting the reconstruction of the foundations of mathematics.